Ontological Arguments
Anselm's starting point is that God is the being than which none greater can be conceived. The argument goes as follows:
1. God is the greatest conceivable being.One popular objection to this argument is that other greatest conceivable things could be plugged into this argument. For example, the Lost Island is the greatest conceivable island and thus exists. But not so fast, how would an island be the greatest of its kind? How many miles of beach would it have, potentially infinite? Certain types of perfection do not have an instrinsic maximal value, and thus not just any old greatest conceivable thing can be plugged into this argument. But this objection might cut both ways, since some of God's alleged great-making properties don't seem to admit of instrinsic maxima (eg., perfectly loving). In other words, some intrinsic great-making properties may be problematic for this argument.
2. God exists in the understanding.
3. To exist in reality is better than merely to exist in understanding.
4. Thus, if God exists merely in the understanding, then we can conceive of something greater than God, namely a being just like God, but who also exists.
5. But it is impossible to conceive of a being that is greater than the greatest conceivable being.
6. Thus it is impossible that God exists merely in the understanding.
7. Thus God exists in reality as well as in the understanding.
8. Thus God exists.
But is existence a property at all, much less a great-making property? Kant answered in the negative. To ascribe properties to something presupposes its existence.[1] Murray and Rea point out that Kant is assuming that a precondition (for ascribing other properties) can't itself be a property. "Taking up space" is a precondition for having the property of "being red", but "taking up space" is also itself a property. Likewise with existence, except that existence the precondition for all properties (or so Kant argues). Perhaps it is, but this still doesn't show that existence can't be a property. On the other hand, Rea and Murray don't give any arguments in favor of predicating existence either (my guess is this gets deep under the hood of language). So, I'm not sure about Kant's objection.
Some maintain that the ontological argument begs the question. The first premise would need to be modified to be conditional. "[5.1**] For anything to count as God, that thing would have to be the greatest conceivable being." But now the conclusion only says "Thus anything that counts as God would have to exist."
Recent work in the area of philosophy known as modal logic has produced a new rendition of this argument. Modal logic deals with claims/inferences that are about/from possibility and necessity. Rea and Murray define a possible world as "a comprehensive description of the way the universe might be...the maximally comprehensive description of our universe is the actual world." Next, they define a necessary being and necessary property possession. A necessary being is one that would exist in all possible worlds. A being possesses a property necessarily if it has that property in all possible worlds. For example, Arnold Schwarzenegger is 6 feet tall ascribes a property to Arnold, but Arnold could be 5 feet tall in some possible world. On the other hand, Arnold Schwarzenegger is a person ascribes a property to Arnold that holds in all possible worlds. Hmm, but what about Kant's objection? Arnold can only hold a necessary property in the worlds that he exists in, right? Consider the proposition Arnold is an existent. Is existence a property or not? Not sure what Plantinga says on this issue, but here is the modal argument:
5.20 God is the greatest possible beingPremise 5.23 is susceptible to refutation. For instance, some philosophical theologians think that the concept of a greatest possible being entails a contradiction. Thus, it is not possible that the greatest possible being exists. In other words, if a perfect being is shown to be conceptually impossible, this argument fails. A more modest critic might just insist that we withhold judgement on this argument until we have resolved all the apparent contradictions in philosophical theology. But a powerful rebuttal can be given to both critics here. Since premise 5.23 asserts the possibility that the greatest possible being exists, then the response to conceptual impossibility is to adjust our concept accordingly to be in line with what is possible. Does omnipotence and impeccability entail a contradiction? No problem, just adjust the concept. The point here is that some philosophical concepts are hard to pin down and declare impossible. The concept of the greatest possible being, by its very nature, is damn near impossible to deem impossible.
5.21 The greatest possible being is one that possesses all perfections necessarily
5.22 Necessary existence is a perfection
5.23 It is possible that the greatest possible being exists
5.24 If it is possible that the greatest possible being exists, then that being exists necessarily
5.25 God exists necessarily
5.26 God exists
But someone can still object that necessary existence is impossible. After all, the being must exist (or possess existence?) in all possible worlds for this argument to work. Rea and Murray don't think that any convincing arguments have been offered in this direction. A few references would have been nice. But regardless, it looks like "its possible until shown impossible" isn't exactly a compelling reason to accept 5.23 either. But, compelling reasons are hard to come by in these types of arguments (or so it seems to me at least).
[1] Alvin Plantinga, in God, Freedom and Evil (1977), proceeds meticulously through the details of Kant's objections in a section entitled "The Irrelevance of Kant's Objection."
2 comments:
I found your blog via M and M.
Just a quick question - is this not a definition of an idealized hypothetical God rather an actual God as described by the major Abrahamic texts ?
I thought that William Lane-Craigs definition of a moral God had the same problem too.
Would the perfect God really have framed the fourth commandment in Exodus 2 v5 admitting jealousy as a motive ? That's just an example.
The perfect God sounds like a nice God, but to assert that that is the Christian God just doesn't seem to be correct.
Maybe I'm misunderstanding something.
Paul,
I'm not sure how the perfect God being the Christian God is relevant to this argument at all. That would be like saying an argument for whether or not the President of the United States has the authority to creates new laws is relevant to discussions on whether Obama is actually the current President.
This argument concerns the concept of God as a perfect being (just as we can talk about the concept of a President without references a specific instance). This is indeed a concept that is endorsed in those texts (though Islam differs a bit with respect to God's goodness and how it plays out).
You can Google around to see the meaning of the word translated as "jealousy" in Exodus 5. This verse was actually cited Oprah Winfrey as a reason she left her childhood faith believe it or not. I think a closer inspection removes any alleged problems here.
Every description of God in the Bible is not intended to convey a literal truth about his nature. For instance, when we hear that "God upholds Israel by his right hand" we should not conclude that God has a right hand.
Besides that, it might go either way here. One might reject a particular description of God in scripture on the grounds that it doesn't mesh with what a perfect being would do. But, it also seems to me that God might have good reasons to do a lot of things that at face value don't seem "right" to us.
William Lane Craig's definition of God as a moral God is exactly the same Anselmian definition mentioned here. I don't see the "problem" with this.
Post a Comment